On the Trinity

Free download. Book file PDF easily for everyone and every device. You can download and read online On the Trinity file PDF Book only if you are registered here. And also you can download or read online all Book PDF file that related with On the Trinity book. Happy reading On the Trinity Bookeveryone. Download file Free Book PDF On the Trinity at Complete PDF Library. This Book have some digital formats such us :paperbook, ebook, kindle, epub, fb2 and another formats. Here is The CompletePDF Book Library. It's free to register here to get Book file PDF On the Trinity Pocket Guide.

The first Trinity puzzle is that of explaining how we can attribute full divinity to the Persons of the Trinity without either compromising monotheism or undermining claims about the distinctness of Trinitarian persons. Orthodox accounts of the Trinity hover uneasily between Sabellianism—which construes Trinitarian Persons as mere phases, aspects or offices of one God—and tri-theism, according to which the Persons are three Gods. Tri-theism is unacceptable since it is incompatible with the historical Christian commitment to monotheism inherited from the Hebrew tradition.

The fundamental problem for Trinitarian orthodoxy is to develop a doctrine of the Trinity that fits in the space between Sabellianism or other versions of Monarchianism and tri-theism. For Social Trinitarians in particular the problem has been one of articulating an account of the Trinity that affirms the individuality of the Persons and their relationships with one another without lapsing into tri-theism.

Christians hold that there are properties that distinguish the Persons.

First, there are intra—Trinitarian relational properties the Persons have in virtue of their relations to other Trinitarian Persons: the Father begets the Son, but the Son does not beget the Son; the Spirit proceeds from the Father and the Son but neither the Father nor the Son proceeds from the Father and the Son.

The Second Person of the Trinity becomes incarnate, is born, suffers, dies, is buried, rises from the dead and ascends to the Father. According to orthodox doctrine, however, the same is not true of the Father or Holy Spirit and, indeed, the doctrine that the Father became incarnate, suffered and died is the heresy of patripassionism. According to Latin Trinitarians, God, the Trinity, is an individual rather than a community of individuals sharing the same divine nature and each Person of the Trinity is that individual.

Given this account however, the trick is to block inferences from the ascription of properties characteristic of one Trinitarian Person to the ascription of those properties to other Persons. Moreover, since it is held that the Persons cannot be individuated by their worldly activities, Latin Trinitarians, whose project is to explain the distinctions between Persons, must develop an account of the intra—Trinitarian relations that distinguish them—a project which is at best speculative.

Supposing that we tread the fine line, and succeed in affirming both the participation of Trinitarian Persons in one God and their distinctness. Orthodoxy then requires, in addition, that we hold the Persons of the Trinity to be equal in power, knowledge, goodness and all properties pertaining to divinity other than those that are specific to the Persons individually. This poses problems when it comes to divine agency. In the absence of a tie-breaker, it is hard to see how the Trinity can get anything done!

This is a difficulty for Social Trinitarians in particular insofar as they understand the Trinitarian Persons as distinct centers of consciousness and will whose projects might be incompatible. Even if Social Trinitarians avoid Subordinationism, the descending account of the Trinity according to which the defining characteristic of the Father is that of being the Source of Trinitarian Persons has theological ramifications which, in the end, resulted in the defining controversy between Eastern and Western churches concerning the Filioque clause. The original version of the Creed formulated by the councils of Nicea and Constantinople, declares that the Holy Spirit proceeds from the Father ek tou Patros ek poreuomenon.

The Filioque Clause, affirming that the Holy Spirit proceeds from the Father and the Son ex Patri Filioque procedit , which first appeared in the profession of faith formulated at the Council of Toledo in , spread throughout Gaul and eventually become normative in the West, was firmly rejected by the Eastern churches on the grounds that it undermined the doctrine that the Father was the Source of Trinitarian Persons and the personality of the Holy Spirit.

If he can, then the participation of the Son in the generation of the Holy Spirit is superfluous and so there is no reason to accept the Filioque Clause. Photios, representing the Eastern tradition, assumes a descending account of the Trinity according to which the characteristic hypostatic property of the Father is his role as the Source of the other Trinitarian Persons. He assumes in addition that all properties of Trinitarian Persons are such that they are either generic properties of divinity, and so are shared by all Persons, or hypostatic properties possessed uniquely by the Persons they characterize.


  1. 50 Scrumptious Breakfast Recipes for Students (Delicious Non-Vegetarian Diabetic Recipes Book 1).
  2. Amenities for every lifestyle;
  3. Understanding The Trinity - esprosgolddistcon.gq.
  4. Malice and Remorse?
  5. “Trinity School closely approximates the ideal in education.”.
  6. Alicia Big Boobs Sex Diva of DivineBreasts.com.
  7. Finishing Touches : A Play in Two Acts.

It follows from these assumptions that the Filioque Clause should be rejected. Photios and other Eastern theologians worried also that the Western account of the Trinity undermined the personal character of the Holy Spirit. According to one metaphor, widely employed in the West, the Father, Son and Holy Spirit are analogous to the Lover, the Beloved and the Love between them. It does not seem to be so since there is no compelling reason why we should regard the property of being the Source of Trinitarian persons as one that confers superior status or authority on its possessor.

Some parents are smarter, better looking, and richer than their children; others are dumber, uglier, and poorer. To the extent that the role of the Father as the Source of Trinitarian Persons is analogous to human parenthood there is no reason to regard the Father as in any respect superior to the other Persons and it is hard to see what other reason could be given for this view. Nevertheless, the descending Trinity picture lends itself to subordinatist interpretations in a way that the flat Trinity model does not.

Trinity High Manchester #Back2School Competition - Pie Radio

Finally, Christians hold that God is personal —the subject of psychological states. But what is personal: the Trinity in toto or the Persons individually? The Litany, which addresses the Persons individually, and the Trinity in toto suggests all of the above:.

A Discursion on Dawkins

O God the Father, Creator of heaven and earth; Have mercy upon us. O God the Son, Redeemer of the world; Have mercy upon us. O holy, blessed, and glorious Trinity, one God: Have mercy upon us. But this does not seem to be a coherent position.

About the Wesley Center Online

If the Father, Son and Holy Spirit are distinct centers of consciousness, the sorts of beings to whom one can reasonably appeal for mercy, and the Trinity is a divine society as Social Trinitarians suggest, it would seem that the Trinity could not itself be personal in any robust sense. After invoking the Father, Son and Holy Ghost, the invocation of the Trinity seems superfluous—as if I were to ask permission to build a fence on our adjoining property lines from each of my neighbors and then get them together to ask permission of them as a group. On the face of it Latin Trinitarians have an easier time explaining what is personal: it is God, the Trinity and the Persons are individually personal to the extent that each is God.

The invocations in the Litany are indeed redundant because all four invoke no one other than God, but that is just a matter of poetic license. Nevertheless, some Christians, in particular Eastern Christians who are sympathetic to the Social Trinitarianism, worry that some metaphors Latin Trinitarians exploit undermine the personal character of the Holy Spirit. Who was praying to whom? On the Latin Trinitarian account it seems that, insofar as we identify Jesus with the Second Person of the Trinity, God was simply talking to himself.

The doctrine of the Trinity, as noted earlier, is motivated by the Christian conviction that Jesus was, in some sense, divine.


  • Strategy and Plans (Leadership Challenges for Servant Leaders Book 7).
  • Trinity On The Green | An Episcopal parish in the heart of downtown New Haven.
  • We Are God;
  • A Vicky Hill Exclusive!.
  • Jesus however was born, suffered under Pontius Pilate, was crucified, died and was buried; he did not understand Chinese; he believed that David was the author of all the Psalms. These properties are, it would seem, incompatible with divinity and, indeed, there appear to be a great many predicates that are true of Jesus which, it would seem, could not be true of God and vice versa. This is the Jesus Predicate Problem: we do not want to ascribe all the predicates that are true of Jesus to God simpliciter or, in particular, to God the Father.

    We do not, for example, want to hold that the Father suffered on the Cross—the heresy of Patripassionism. God, as traditionally understood is impassible —he cannot be subject to suffering, pain or harm. Moreover God has no beginning in time or end, and is, according to most orthodox accounts atemporal insofar as he is eternal rather than merely everlasting: he exists outside of time in what is, from the perspective of his subjectivity, the eternal now.

    In general, there are a range of predicates that are true of Jesus that, we want to hold, are not true of God the Father or of the Holy Spirit, and which we would hesitate to ascribe to God simpliciter insofar as they appear to be inconsistent with essential features of divinity.

    http://mebelhause.com/tmp/afanaseva/1191.html

    BBC - Religions - Christianity: The Trinity

    Since Monarchians cannot use Trinitarian doctrine to block these inferences they use Christology to do the job—by either adopting very high Christologies or very low ones. To see how this works, consider Apollarianism, an ultra-high Christology rejected at the Council of Constantinople in and again at the Council of Chalcedon in at which Christological doctrine was formulated. According to this heterodox view, the historical Jesus was a human being who had the Logos plugged into the place that would normally be occupied by a human rational soul.

    Strictly speaking, what these predicates are true of is not Christ but only of the body he used for a time to conduct his worldly operations. Consequently, they do not pass to the Logos or to other Persons of the Trinity, so there is no problem. The other way to drive the wedge between the Father and the bearer of Jesus predicates is by adopting an ultra-low Christology, that is, by kicking Christ out of the Godhead altogether.

    If Christ, the bearer of Jesus predicates is not divine, problematic Jesus predicates do not pass to the Father, or to God simpliciter, so there is no problem. Interestingly, Christians have historically rejected ultra-high Christologies on the grounds that they undermine soteriology. Anselm makes the same point in Cur Deus Homo? Whatever we think of this sort of argument it was for this reason that Christians worried about Christologies that failed to recognize the full humanity of Christ.

    Christians who could not accept either ultra-high or ultra-low Christologies attempted to circumvent the Jesus Predicate Problem by rejecting the ultra-tight Monarchian view of the Trinity. So, writing more than a century before Nicea, Hippolytus suggested that Hereclitean contradictions could be avoided by a Trinitarian doctrine that created enough logical space between the Persons to block inferences from the character of Christ, the Second Person of the Trinity, to claims about the character of the other Persons, the Father in particular.

    Given a Subordinationist account on the descending model according to which the Second Person is a semi-divine mediating figure there is no problem assigning troublesome Jesus predicates to him. If ascribing these properties to the Father is bad, ascribing them to the Son thus understood is just as bad. For Christians, at least in the West, Quincunque Vult , commonly known as the Athanasian Creed, defines Trinitarian orthodoxy as follows:.

    And yet they are not three Gods, but one God. Can one consistently believe 1 — 7? Identity is an equivalence relation: it is reflexive, symmetric and transitive, which is to say, for all x, y and z the following hold:. This is bad news. Then it follows from 1 and 2 , by symmetry and transitivity, that the Father is the Son, which contradicts 4.

    Put another way, given LL, 1 entails that God has all the same properties as the Father, including the property of being identical with the Father insofar as everything has the property of self-identity. It follows that, since God has the property of being identical with the Son, the Son also has the property of being identical with the Father, which contradicts 4. These formal features of identity are non-negotiable in the way that the four-sidedness of squares is: God cannot evade them any more than he can make a square with only three sides.

    God can make triangles—and pentagons, chiliagons or figures with any number of sides he pleases—but he cannot make such things squares. Identity is a relation between objects; in particular, it is the relation that everything bears to itself and to no other thing.

    Understanding The Trinity

    In a true identity statement the nouns or noun phrases on either sides of the identity pick out the very same thing. Similarly, 1' and 2' do not imply that the Father is the Son so there is no contradiction. However, 1' — 3' just say that the Father, Son and Holy Spirit are each divine, in the way that 8 just says that Ducati is canine, and this leaves open the possibility that there are two, or three Gods involved.

    They do not explain what makes the Persons one God or provide any rationale for 7.

    The Trinity

    This is the concern Gregory of Nyssa addressed in his response to Ablabius, who worried that understanding the unity of Trinitarian persons in terms of their sharing the property of divinity implied Tri-theism:. The argument which you state is something like this: Peter, James, and John, being in one human nature, are called three men: and there is no absurdity in describing those who are united in nature, if they are more than one, by the plural number of the name derived from their nature.

    The question is, as I said, very difficult to deal with.


    1. How To Become A Private Investigator - Lesson 1.
    2. Mirror Shards: Volume One?
    3. Researching Your Colonial New England Ancestors!
    4. On the Trinity, Triangulation, and Islam?
    5. THE HOLY TRINITY.

    That which is not thus circumscribed is not enumerated, and that which is not enumerated cannot be contemplated in multitude.